Brian Arthur has trouble seeing where innovation
and technological progress fit into the view that the “discovery” phase of
Scientific knowledge is all over bar the shouting.
If the evolutionary account is right, it doesn’t work like that, and we’re the better for it, he says.
rian Arthur’s The Nature of Technology is somewhat ponderous in
its beginning (and in truth, throughout) but all the same is most encouraging
in its epistemological disposition - assuming as it does the recursivity of
society and technology, rather than toting the (conventional) view that one is
strictly a product of the other. This points you towards a path-dependent model
for not just technology, but society and indeed knowledge itself.
But for
some, this is dangerous stuff. It leads in turn to uncomfortable conclusions
(at least for the neo-enlightenment brigade) which open the door to all that
crazy post-modern stuff.
Because he
doesn’t have to, Arthur doesn’t go there, but he does cast a kindly glance at Thomas Kuhn. (I like people who cast kindly
glances at Thomas Kuhn: these days they’re few and far between).
Arthur doesn’t
have to go there (at first) because technology, as implemented, is almost by
definition infra-paradigmatic: if “science” is its philosophical principle,
technology is its practical implementation - very much the sort of thing Nancy Cartwright would call a “nomological
machine”: a construction designed to give a dependable result in a constrained
set of circumstances, where the machine not only prescribes the parameters for
a “successful” result, but constrains the environment and operating
circumstances in which outcomes are generated to ensure the result is within
those parameters, and then, reliably, forces that outcome. (A technology that
is unable to force an outcome within its own parameters for a successful result
is simply a machine that doesn’t work).
But this
leaves a gap. If technology is merely the practical implementation of “normal
science”, it has a hard time explaining innovation. As Arthur puts it:
“Combination
[of existing technologies] cannot be the only mechanism behind technology’s
evolution. If it were, modern technologies such as radar or magnetic resource
imaging ... would be created out of bow-drills and pottery firing techniques,
or whatever else we deem to have existed at the start of technological time.”
“If technology is merely the practical implementation of “normal science”, it has a hard time explaining innovation.”
The problem,
which Arthur specifically sets out to address, is how to account for the “onward”
development of technology. Arthur is clear that it is path-dependent (“had we
uncovered phenomena over historical times in a different sequence, we would have
developed different technologies”) but even this insight, I think, risks
undercooking the importance of the narrative conversation: it is not just that
combinations of technologies through time let us further uncover existing
theories and give us better and more powerful and enabling answers to our
original questions; they prompt completely new questions: they afford new ways
of looking at the world. New ways of looking generate new opportunities, and
new problems.
This is a
significant point.
For example:
prior to the digital age, categorisation of information was a difficult and
inherently limited (and, actually, biased) thing: the physical nature of
information storage (books) dictated a single taxonomy and a single hierarchy,
and required commitment to a single filing taxonomy (without owning more than
one copy of a book, you can’t file it in two places). Digitisation changed that
forever: the Dewey Decimal system - brilliant in its design
though it undoubtedly was - solves a problem we no longer have, but at the cost
of forcing our hand in a way we no longer need. Digital technology has enabled
us to entirely re-evaluate what information really is.
As he goes
on, Arthur explicitly keeps in mind two “side issues” that constantly recur in
writings about technology: the analogy to Darwin’s program of evolution, on one hand, and
the analogy to Kuhn’s theories of scientific revolution on the other. But these
are, to my mind, different articulations of the same idea: that “questions” and
“answers” (whether you characterise these as “environmental features” and “biological
adaptations which evolve to deal with them”, or “observational conundrums” and “scientific
theories which purport to explain them”) are, to a large extent,
interdependent: something is only a conundrum if it appears to contradict the
prevailing group of theories. What both Darwin and Kuhn suggest is that “linear
progress” - insofar as it implies a predetermined goal to which an evolutionary
algorithm is progressing - is a misconceived idea. Evolutionary development is
better characterised as a move away from the status quo, rather than a move
towards anything (in hindsight, both will seem the same; to confuse them is a
fundamental error).
Yet, and
while Arthur clearly recognises this, he does continue to frame his explanatory
theory in terms of “forward progress”, as if that is the “conundrum” to be
solved. The thing is, even our traditional conception of it has this the wrong
way round: “the invention of the jet engine” wasn’t what was going on; it was “the
invention of a way to fly in thinner air”. The jet engine was the first
solution arrived at that met that purpose (as, in a totally different context, Richard Susskind elegantly points out, when you
shop for a Black & Decker, it isn’t a drill you want; it’s a hole).
Technology (and science, and biology) isn’t an end, it’s a means. The more
means you have, the more ends are available to you.
“The implications of this are striking. They completely undermine the idea of technology as a “forwardly moving” phenomenon.”
I had
therefore wondered whether Arthur had missed a trick in his account of
technology - the fact that any novel solution to an old problem creates new
questions that we did not think - or need - to ask previously. But as his book
closes and he views technology through the prism of the economy (on his theory
the two are independent; the former is not merely the handmaiden of the
latter), he nails this, too:
“The coming
of novel technologies does not just disrupt the status quo by finding new
combinations that are better versions of the goods and methods we use. It sets
up a train of technological accommodations and of new problems, and in doing so
it creates new opportunity niches that call forth fresh combinations which in
turn introduce further technologies - and further problems.”
The
implications of this are striking. They completely undermine the idea of
technology as a “forwardly moving” phenomenon. It recalibrates to our changing
needs and perceptions, just as we recalibrate to the changing perspectives and
vistas it affords us. That is a million miles away from Ray Kurzweil’s carefully plotted (and in your
correspondent’s opinion, absurd) logarithmic charts of technological progress
that will see machines - and, on Kurzweil’s account, eventually the cosmos
itself - “wake up”.
Even if
there were no other reasons (and there are many), one reason for favouring
Arthur’s less ambitious (but actually more radical) view is its humanity.
Arthur closes the book with a neat bit of lit crit: the forces of good and evil
in Star Wars, he observes, can be differentiated by
their relationship with technology: the Empire’s clinical, cold, efficient,
androidal heartlessness - against the temperamental, jury rigged, cantankerous
and fallible technology of the rebels: in one case technology is our weapon: it
relies on us, on our skill, on our judgment and our humanity: we are the
necessary homunculus; in the other the humans are, more or less, the “necessary
evil” - the impediment to the technology achieving its ends.
Recognising that the special sauce in technology is, for the time being at least, the bit supplied by the meatware, is a comforting thought.
Recognising that the special sauce in technology is, for the time being at least, the bit supplied by the meatware, is a comforting thought.
No comments:
Post a Comment